Humanitarian intervention(s)
The notion of humanitarian intervention has deeply
changed over time. Both for the general public and policy-makers, and for the
scholars. The following is an analysis of three papers written by M. Finnemore,
M. Mandelbaum and S. Hoffmann respectively on this concept, each one with a
specific vision of the concerning issue.
Fundamentally, for Martha Finnemore on Constructing Norms of Humanitarian
Intervention, this concept is a practical consequence of the dynamic
evolution of norms concerning international military interferences.
The author believes that since realist and liberal
approaches to the international system understand that states are bound to its
economic and/or geostrategic interests, humanitarian intervention does not fit
very well in these two theories. Therefore, as in many historical occasions no
obvious national interest was found in the justification of third state
interventions (such as it happened in 1989, Somalia, by the United States),
Finnemore argues that those acts were due to a change in “normative standards
(…) concerning appropriate ends and means of military intervention” (Columbia
U.P., 1996, p.155).
In this document it is conceived that norms shape
interests and then interests shape action. Justifications of the interventions
clearly reflect the normative context, that is, shared values and expectations.
From a historical point of view, in the XIX century
and in the first ¾ of the XX, the interventions with some humanitarian
justifications were merely unilateral. If in a case the interventions were
multilateral was because of an evident strategic interest of the groups of
states.
Afterwards, the change into multilateral humanitarian
interventions was partly due to the decolonization process that provided the
self-determination right together with the sovereign statehood to ex-colonized
peoples; that meant that unilateral interventions would be extremely difficult
to justify in front of a different normative context (the UN Charter for
instance) in respect to these new nations. Therefore, after 1945, the practical
translation of Responsibility to Protect, humanitarian intervention, became multilateral
in order to legitimize itself. And the United Nations was the best umbrella
under which R2P should be carried out, following Finnemore’s thought.
We can see the evolution towards the contemporary
concept of humanitarian intervention in the historical examples. First, mainly
in the 19th century, interventions were narrowed into the national
interest of the European states that coincided with the normative context of
the religious and/or ethnic ties between Western societies and the victims of
which states were supposedly responsible: in practice, Christians and populations
in the East linked to European peoples. Nevertheless, norms did in a certain
way shape the strategic interests of states. Then, the concept of those
deserving intervention broadened as the Western conception of humanity universalized including non-Christians
and non-Europeans.
In the paper, Finnemore emphasizes that the scholar
world should clarify better the sources of change in the normative arena by
studying concrete cases. Furthermore, the writer states that the relation
between power and norms “may not be so simple” (Ibid., p.185) referring to the
Gramscian conception that normative structures are framed by and for the most
powerful. She argues that the dynamic origins of norms are for instance public
opinion, the media, and international institutions.
In the paper written by Mandelbaum, as stated in its
title “Foreign Policy as Social Work”, he understands humanitarian intervention
as a prolongation of the policies of the national governments of states. In the
case given, the author centers in analyzing US interventions during the Clinton
Administrations (Foreign Affairs, January-February 1996, p.16-32).
The initial proposals of President Clinton were
playing the role of social work power
in the international arena. However, Clinton jeopardized this path of focusing
on the humanitarian needs of the periphery by not paying attention to the
domestic public support. This is because, as said in the article, Americans
tend more to back humanitarian initiatives when they come along with US national
interests, such as it happened in the Cold War. Then, when Clinton tried to present
his humanitarian interventions to the domestic public, he and his
Administrations could not justify in any case the appeal to national interest. Mendelbaum
shows this illustrating the issues of Haiti, Somalia and Bosnia: the former two
have no strategic interest for the US and even less in the post-Cold War era,
and Clinton abandoned his bellicose discourse with Serbia following the Dayton
Accords.
To summarize, Mandelbaum’s work conceives humanitarian
intervention another branch of domestic
politics.
On his behalf, Hoffmann articulates humanitarian
intervention as a result of socially constructed norms of what is acceptable or
not in the world order (Foreign Affairs, March-April 1996, p.172-175). Also, he
does not separate interests and values; criticizing Mendelbaum on his deterministic
conception of what is the national security concept, and states that this one
is shaped by policymakers.
Moreover, as said, Hoffmann’s conception of
humanitarian intervention is rooted in the vast interconnection and interdependence
of the new global society. Therefore, he proposes two key causes for humanitarian
intervention: (a) important threat for peace and security in the region or the
world and/or (b) a massive violation of human rights. Obviously, as constructs,
as not self-evident, they are susceptible to change, despite this dynamic
factor, the author believes that these two elements are not acceptable
according to his values and probably to the ones of many people too. In
addition, this clear idea of intervention was not exposed well to the public by
President Clinton, and that was a main issue that lead to his foreign policy failure.
In conclusion, we see humanitarian intervention as a
practical consequence of the evolution of a norm by Finnemore, as a branch of
domestic politics by Mendelbaum, and as a result of socially and globally constructed
norms by Hoffmann.
References
1. Mandelbaum,
Michael, “Foreign Policy as Social Work”, Foreign Affairs, January-February
1996.
2.Hoffmann,
Stanley, “In Defence of Mother Teresa”, Foreign Affairs, March-April
1996.
3.Finnemore,
Martha, “Constructing Norms of Humanitarian Intervention” in Katzenstein,
Peter, The Culture of National Security, New York, Columbia U.P., 1996.
Cap comentari:
Publica un comentari a l'entrada